英文摘要
|
Gregor Mendel, the famous nineteenth-century Austrian botanist, has been considered the discoverer of laws of classical (Mendelian) genetics. Several historians of biology recently began to argue that Mendel had never discovered Mendel's laws. If he did not discover Mendel's laws at all, what is his discovery? What is his contribution to science? To answer the above questions, one has to re-examine the whole story of his experimentation and the origin of classical genetics. The philosophical problems involved in scientific discoveries have also to be reconsidered.By and large, two current but different views of historiography have been applied to write the history of Mendel's discovery and the origin of classical genetics. The evidence-based historiography sees the history of science as a process filled by discoveries of novel theories and facts, exclusion of errors, and accumulation and progress of knowledge. It holds that Mendel did discover Mendel's laws. The discovery is therefore his greatest contribution to science. In contrast, Kuhnian paradigm-based historiography attributes Mendel's works to an old experimental tradition of breeding and hybridization. It claims that Mendel's experiment was not about heredity and he was not a Mendelian himself. In addition, most ideas about heredity in Mendel's time were dominated by the developmentalist paradigm. The classical genetics based on Mendel's laws is a new paradigm entirely different from developmentalism.In this study, I argue that the paradigm-based historiography provides a better explanation of the history of genetics than its evidence-based rival. Yet, as it seems to neglect the independent role played by experimentation, the paradigm-based version of Mendel's experimental work is not adequate. To give a more plausible account of the place of Mendel's experiment in the history of genetics, I develop a model-based concept of experimental discovery and demonstrate that Mendel's achievement embodies a typical pattern of experimental discovery.
|
参考文献
|
-
Chen, Ruey-Lin(2004).Testing through Realizable Model.NTU Philosophical Review,27,67-117.
連結:
-
陳瑞麟(2005)。科學現象的觀察與建構。東吳哲學學報,11,57-98。
連結:
-
陳瑞麟(2007)。科學實驗的輻射發展:重構早期電學實驗的歷史。歐美研究,37(4),535-591。
連結:
-
Bateson, William (1909). Mendel's Principles of Heredity. Cambridge: Cambridge University.
-
Bowler, Peter J.(1989).The Mendelian Revolution: The Emergence of Hereditarian Comcepts in Modern Science and Society.Baltimore:The John Hopkins University.
-
Carlson, Elof A.(2004).Mendel's Legacy: The Origin of Classical Genetics.Cold Springer Harbor, NY:Cold Springer Harbor Laboratory Press.
-
Chen, Ruey-Lin(2007).The Structure of Experimentation and the Replication Degree: Reconsidering the replication of Hertz's cathode ray experiment.Naturalizing Epistemology and Philosophy of Science,Amsterdam, Netherlands:
-
Corcos, Alain,Monaghan, Floyd(1993).Gregor Mendel's Experiments on Plant Hybirds: A Guided Study.New Jersey:Rutger University Press.
-
Hartl, Daniel,Orel, Vitezslav(1992).What Did Gregor Mendel Think He Discovered?.Genetics,131,245-253.
-
Kuhn, Thomas(1970).The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Chicago:The University of Chicago.
-
Magner, Lois N.(2002).A History of the Life Science. Revised and expanded.New York:Marcel Dekker, Inc..
-
Mayr, Ernest(1982).The Growth of Biological Thought.Cambridge, Mass:Harvard University Press.
-
Olby, Robert(1985).Origins of Mendelism.Chicago:University of Chicago.
-
Starr, Cecie、Taggart, Ralph、丁澤民編譯、王偉編譯、張世玲編譯、連慧瑞編譯(1989)。生物學。台北:藝軒圖書。
-
Stern, Curt(Ed.),Sherwood, Eva(Ed. Trans.)(1966).The Origin of Genetics: A Mendel Source Book.San Francisco:W. H. Freeman and Company.
-
Sturtevant, Alfred H.(2001).A History of Genetics.Cold Springer Harbor, NY:Cold Springer Harbor Laboratory Press.
-
Villee, Claude A.(1989).Biology.Philadelphia:Saunders College Publishing.
-
陳瑞麟(2004)。科學理論版本的結構與發展。台北:台大出版中心。
-
陳瑞麟(2003)。科學模型的投射與落實:以人類始祖的探源為例。科學與世界之間:科學哲學論文集,台北:
|