英文摘要
|
The delimitation of fugitive resources has always been a difficult issue. The delimitation of water rights and of patent rights has observable similarities, in terms of both using the central delimitation method and the peripheral delimitation method. Trademark law and copyright law also use the central delimitation approach. These points of overlapping show that the ways to delimit the "object" is not the unique creation of property law or intellectual property; instead, these methods may be common models of human thinking. Legal realists consider property as a bundle of rights, which has become the dominant theory of property in American law. Yet the bundle idea ignores the existence of the "thing" (the resource) and the function of the sign for the delimitation of property. American property law scholar Carol Rose has commented on the importance of restoring "seeing" in property law, a theory we can use to construct the basic model of the semantic relation of property. Later, another property law scholar, Henry E. Smith, proposes to restore the status of the "thing" in property law. Smith proposes to define property as the law of "modular things": modules (boundaries) serve as the bounds of the thing and the bounds of the rights. The construction of modular thing is the construction of the semantic relation of property. Professor Hansmann and Kraakman also remind us of the function of convention for the delimitation of rights. From the reconstruction of property law theory, three interacting elements have emerged-the rights, the thing, and the sign. The concept of semiosis, as proposed by semiotics, can serve as a framework to connect the three elements. Saussure's semiology is closer to the realist "bundle of rights" theory, since both of them disregard the thing. Peirce's semiotics, capable of incorporating physical resources into the semiotic structure, is a better candidate for constructing the property relation. Explicated from the perspective of semiosis, property in general embodies the semiotic relation among the resource (thing), the boundaries, and the rights. As to patents, the same relation is among the invention, the patent, and the patent rights. The way to delimit patent rights is to apply the criterial model of meaning and conventionalism in order to determine the corresponding scope of patent rights. In principle, this is a formal semantic operation; however, in case an inconsistency happens between the scope of rights and the object (the invention), the court may deviate from formal semantic operation and go back to the original contexts. In patent law, this is to use the doctrine of equivalents and the reverse doctrine of equivalents to solve the problems of over-inclusion and under-inclusion. Finally, this article provides a legal positivist explanation for these phenomena.
|
参考文献
|
-
Alfonso, A.(2010).Water rights in the Marcellus Shale and how they concern oil and gas companies.Appalachian Natural Resources Law Journal,4,1-33.
-
Burk, D. L.,Lemley, M. A.(2009).Fence posts or sign posts? Rethinking patent claim construction?.University of Pennsylvania Law Review,157,1743-1799.
-
Chang, Y.-C.(2014).An economic and comparative analysis of specificatio (the accession doctrine).European Journal of Law and Economics,39,225-243.
-
Chisum, D. S.(1998).The scope of protection after the Supreme Court's Warner-Jenkinson decision: the fair protection-certainty conundrum.Santa Clara Computer and High Technology Law Journal,14,1-62.
-
Choe, O. S.(2004).Appurtenancy reconceptualized: managing water in an era of scarcity.The Yale Law Journal,113,1909-1953.
-
Collins, K. E.(2008).The reach of literal claim scope into after-arising technology: on thing construction and the meaning of meaning.Connecticut Law Review,41,493-559.
-
Deledalle, G.(2000).Charles S. Peirce's philosophy of signs: essays in comparative semiotics.Bloomington, IN:Indiana University Press.
-
Fromer, J. C.(2009).Claiming intellectual property.University of Chicago Law Review,76,719-796.
-
Furman, J. D.(2015).Patent claim construction under Teva v. Sandoz: deference at last, or more of the same?.Journal of the Patent and Trademark Office Society,97,579-596.
-
Gopenko, D.(2012).Reconsidering the de novo standard of review in patent claim construction.AIPLA Quarterly Journal,40,315-337.
-
Guest, S.(1991).Ronald Dworkin.Palo Alto, CA:Stanford University Press.
-
Habermas, J.,Rehg, W.(Trans.)(1998).Between facts and norms.Cambridge, MA:The MIT Press.
-
Hansmann, H.,Kraakman, R.(2002).Property, contract, and verification: the numerus clausus problem and the divisibility of rights.The Journal of Legal Studies,31,373-420.
-
Hohfeld, W. N. (1913). Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. The Yale Law Journal, 23, 16-60. doi: 10.2307/785533
-
Hohfeld, W. N. (1917). Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning, The Yale Law Journal, 26, 710-771. doi: 10.2307/786270
-
Kieff, F. S.,Newman, P.,Schwartz, F. H.,Smith, H. E.(2008).Principles of patent law.New York, NY:Foundation Press.
-
LaFrance, M.(2009).Understanding trademark law.New Providence, NJ:Matthew Bender.
-
Leaffer, M. A.(2010).Understanding copyright law.New Providence, NJ:Matthew Bender.
-
Lemley, M. A.(2005).The changing meaning of patent claim terms.Michigan Law Review,104,101-122.
-
Liszka, J. J.(1996).A general introduction to the semeiotic of Charles Sanders Peirce.Bloomington, IN:Indiana University Press.
-
Lutz, K. B. (1938). Evolution of claims of U.S. patents, part 1. Journal of Patent Office Society, 20, 134-155.
-
Lutz, K. B. (1938). Evolution of claims of U.S. patents, part 3. Journal of Patent Office Society, 20, 457-489.
-
Lutz, K. B. (1938). Evolution of claims of U.S. patents, part 2. Journal of Patent Office Society, 20, 377-399.
-
Madison, M. J.(2005).Law as design: objects, concepts, and digital things.Case Western Reserve Law Review,56,381-478.
-
Marmor, A.(ed.),Soames, S.(ed.)(2011).Philosophical foundations of language in the law.Oxford, UK:Oxford University Press.
-
McCarthy, J. T.(2016).McCarthy on trademarks and unfair competition.St. Paul, MN:Westlaw.
-
Merrill, T. W.,Smith, H. E.(2010).The Oxford introduction to U.S. law: property.New York, NY:Oxford University Press.
-
Merrill, T. W.,Smith, H. E.(2011).Making Coasean property more Coasean.The Journal of Law and Economics,54,S77-S104.
-
Mills, J. G., III,Reiley, R. C., III,Highley, R. C.,Rosenberg, P. D.(2016).Patent law fundamentals.St. Paul, MN:Westlaw.
-
Moy, R. C.(2013).Moy's Walker on patents.St. Paul, MN:Westlaw.
-
Mueller, J. M.(2006).An introduction to patent law.New York, NY:Aspen.
-
Nard, C. A.(2000).A theory of claim interpretation.Harvard Journal of Law and Technology,14,1-82.
-
Outhwaite, W.(1994).Habermas: a critical introduction.Palo Alto, CA:Stanford University Press.
-
Patry, W. F.(2016).Patry on copyright.St. Paul, MN:Westlaw.
-
Peirce, C. S. (1940). The philosophy of Peirce: selected writings (J. Buchler ed.). New York, NY: Harcourt.
-
Rose, C. M.(1994).Property and persuasion: theory, and rhetoric of ownership.Boulder, CO:Westview.
-
Rose, C. M.(1990).Energy and efficiency in the realignment of common-law water rights.The Journal of Legal Studies,19,261-296.
-
Rose, C. M.(2008).From H2O to CO2: lessons of water Rights for carbon trading.Arizona Law Review,50,91-110.
-
Short, T. L.(2007).Peirce's theory of signs.Cambridge, UK:Cambridge University Press.
-
Smith, H. E.(2007).Intellectual property as property: Delineating Entitlements in Information.The Yale Law Journal,116,1742-1822.
-
Smith, H. E.(2012).Property as the law of things.Harvard Law Review,125,1691+1726.
-
Smith, H. E.(2009).Institutions and indirectness in intellectual property.University of Pennsylvania Law Review,157,2083-2133.
-
Squires, L. B.(1985).Unused riparian water rights in Washington-Department of Ecology v. Abott, 103 WN.2d 686, 694 P.2d 1071.Washington Law Review,60,787-803.
-
Thomas, G. A.(1996).Conserving aquatic biodiversity: a critical comparison of legal tools for augmenting streamflows in California.Stanford Environmental Law Journal,15,3-58.
-
丁爾蘇(2011)。符號學與跨文化研究。上海:復旦大學出版社。
-
王敏銓(2015)。越界建築與專利均等論。科技法學評論,12(2),1-69。
-
朱建民(1999)。普爾斯。臺北:東大。
-
朱柏松(2010)。民事法問題研究:物權法論。臺北:元照。
-
江耀國(1990)。美國憲法解釋上的原始主義與中立原則。東吳法律學報,6(2),113-143。
-
林誠二(2001)。再論誠實信用原則與權利濫用禁止原則之機能。台灣本土法學雜誌,22,36-61。
-
林遠澤(1995)。真理為何?從哈伯瑪斯真理共識理論的實用轉向論真理的規範性涵義。歐美研究,35(2),363-404。
-
哈特、許家馨譯、李冠宜譯(2010)。法律的概念。臺北:商周。
-
科尼利斯.瓦爾、郝長墀譯(2014)。皮爾士。北京:中華書局。
-
莊世同(2011)。從「法概念」到「法理學」:德沃金《法律帝國》導讀。台灣法學雜誌,185,117-125。
-
陳啟桐(2010)。專利判決解析:申請專利範圍解釋(上)。專利師,3,37-48。
-
黃維幸(2016)。法律解釋所為何事?傳統解釋方法的批判。月旦法學雜誌,249,44-69。
-
黃銘傑(2013)。智慧財產法之理論與實務:不同意見書。臺北:元照。
-
劉國讚(2012)。專利法之理論與實用。臺北:元照。
-
蔡明誠(2010)。專利法。臺北:經濟部智慧財產局。
-
簡資修(2012)。寇斯的法律經濟學。台灣法學雜誌,191,80-85。
-
顏厥安(2000)。論證、客觀性與融貫性。月旦法學雜誌,64,33-47。
-
顏厥安(1998)。法與實踐理性。臺北:允晨。
-
顏厥安編、羅昌發編(2009)。理性、思想繼受與法解釋。臺北:元照。
-
羅明通(2014)。著作權法論(II)。臺北:台英國際商務法律事務所。
|